This series was developed from the paper I gave to the Auckland STAANZ Conference: Eschatology and Pneumatology.
In Is Abortion Liberal? I suggested that one cannot simultaneously affirm the harm principle, accept that a fetus is a human being, and support permissive abortion laws. If abortion is homicide then it harms a human being, and the harm principle entails that we should prohibit harmful actions.
Kenneth Einar Himma contests this conclusion. Himma argues that even if one grants that a fetus is a human being, feticide (the killing of a fetus) does not harm the fetus. Consider the doctrine of final punishment which is articulated in chapter 33 of The Westminster Confession of faith.
I. God hath appointed a day, wherein he will judge the world in righteousness by Jesus Christ, to whom all power and judgment is given of the Father. … all persons, that have lived upon earth, shall appear before the tribunal of Christ, to give an account of their thoughts, words, and deeds; and to receive according to what they have done in the body, whether good or evil.
II. The end of God’s appointing this day, is for the manifestation of the glory of his mercy in the eternal salvation of the elect; and of his justice in the damnation of the reprobate, who are wicked and disobedient. For then shall the righteous go into everlasting life, and receive that fullness of joy and refreshing which shall come from the presence of the Lord: but the wicked, who know not God, and obey not the gospel of Jesus Christ, shall be cast into eternal torments, and punished with everlasting destruction from the presence of the Lord, and from the glory of his power.
Himma suggests that, to be plausible, this doctrine should be interpreted so that human beings who lack moral culpability, are saved directly by Gods mercy.
Insofar as culpability presupposes moral knowledge, someone who lacks moral knowledge through no fault of her own is incapable of culpability and is hence exempt from divine punishment. Thus, for example, someone who instantiates a severe cognitive disability is saved without regard to either her behaviour or her attitude towards Christian doctrine. Such a person is saved no matter how she behaves or what she believes.
The same is true of children before they have developed the capacity for moral reasoning. Such persons are incapable of culpability in either deed or belief and, as Abelard puts the point, “Are saved without merit of their own, as for instance, infants, and attain eternal life by grace alone.”1
Himma is not alone in thinking this is the most plausible interpretation of this doctrine. Loraine Boettner, citing Charles Hodge, W. G. T. Shedd, and B. B. Warfield, notes “most Calvinistic theologians have held that those who die in infancy are saved,”2 these theologians, “entertained a charitable hope that since these infants have never committed any actual sin themselves, their inherited sin would be pardoned and they would be saved on wholly evangelical principles.”3
The implication for feticide is obvious; fetuses have not yet developed the capacity for moral reasoning, hence, according to the Eschatological doctrines Himma has sketched, “fetuses that die before birth are, as a matter of moral necessity, saved without regard to personal merit”4 hence they are “as a matter of moral necessity saved without regard to personal merit.” Himma contends that abortion does not harm the fetus but, in fact, benefits it;
It can plausibly be argued that premature death conduces maximally to the fetus’s self-interest. To see this, imagine yourself in the following situation. While in the womb, you are temporarily made fully rational and offered the choice between premature death and the opportunity to live a worldly life. The choice is expressed as follows. Should you choose a premature death, you will immediately experience a profound and eternal bliss – an ecstasy beyond any possible in this world. Should you choose an opportunity to live a worldly life, you will be judged at the end of your life for your deeds and beliefs. If you are judged favorably, you gain eternal bliss; if not, you will suffer eternal torment. You are also told there are many temptations that may lead you down a path that culminates in an unfavorable judgment so that the risk of such torment at the end of your worldly life is substantial. Finally, you are told that, after having made our choice, you will forget everything you have been told. Assume that you have no idea whatsoever of what your post-natal circumstances will be. What should you do? 5
Himma suggest that a rational person would choose to be killed. This is because “the odds of a favourable judgment after a worldly life are probably not in [anyone’s] favor.”6 He notes that if the probability of a favourable judgment is “less than 1. The smallest chance of an unfavorable judgement”7 is multiplied by an infinite cost. Whereas any benefits one gains from a worldly life will be finite.
Consequently, even if one grants that a fetus is a human being, traditional Christian eschatology entails that a fetus is not harmed if it is killed via an induced abortion. The harm principle, however, affirms that the state should permit, and people should have a legal right to engage in, any activity that does not harm another person; consequently, there should be a legal right to procure an induced abortion.
Novus Actus Interveniens Objection
Mark Murphy has argued that Himma’s argument errs by suggesting that the thesis of infant salvation entails that fetuses and infants are not harmed by being prematurely killed. He writes,
If the fetus enjoys the beatific vision upon being aborted … the fetus’ enjoying that good is caused not by the agent’s act of aborting the fetus but by God’s graciously conferring the gift of eternal life on the child. For not every good or evil that occurs downstream from an act counts as a benefit or harm conferred by that act. This is particularly clear in those cases in which the benefit or harm would not have occurred but for some agent’s free intervention. That the causal chain from act to effect is broken by the intervention of a free agent is a standard view, both in common sense’s attribution of responsibility and in the law’s.8
Murphy illustrates the point with an example,
If … a traveler is beaten and left for dead by robbers, is rescued by a Samaritan, and by this transformative experience comes to have a much better life than he or she would otherwise have had, it is nevertheless incorrect to say that the robbers did not harm, or even benefited, the traveler. The robbers merely harmed the traveler; the Samaritan benefited the traveler.9
Murphy here appeals to the common law doctrine novus actus interveniens. He notes that there is a difference between what a person causes and what one foresees will be caused by others in response to what one does. In a discussion of the doctrine of double effect, utilised in post-reformation Catholic casuistry, Donagan suggests that Catholic and Kantian ethicists,
… and in general, all moralists who accept the freedom of the will in a non-combatibilist sense, limit an action’s effects, and a fortiori what its agent intends to bring about in doing it, to those that follow from it in course of nature and the ordinary operation of social institutions, and from the free reactions of others to it. (Thus actions in the ordinary course of business, for example, those of postal officers in delivering a letter that has been mailed, are not counted as free reactions.) The principle on which they do is that a free reaction to an action, is a ‘new action’ (‘novus actus’), the effects of which are their effects, and not those of the action to which they are reactions.10 [Emphasis added]
Donagan does note that another person’s actions can be considered an effect of one’s actions if they follow in the ordinary operation of social institutions. For example, if I mail poison to another person and this kills him or her then I have killed him or her despite the fact that numerous other people’s actions intervened between my action of placing the poison in the mailbox and the person’s death. This is because social institutions are in place whereby the mail service acts as an agent on my behalf and such institutional rules mean that my actions can be attributed to it.11 For similar reasons, taking out a contract to kill another is culpable homicide because the institution of contract means that the killer kills on my behalf and hence I act in his or her actions. In the absence of such institutions, the free actions of others to my actions are not effects that I cause. Donagan notes that in some situations12 a person is culpable of wrongdoing if he does something which he foresees will be met with an immoral action on the part of others. However, he does not cause these actions.
I think this is plausible. Augustine proposed the following example. Suppose a man approaches a woman and tells her that he will kill himself if she refuses to have sex with him. Does that mean that she is a murderer if she refuses?13 Her refusal would not constitute homicide even though his death is a foreseeable result of her choice. Although she foresaw his or her death, she did not cause it. It was caused by the free decision of the tempter to commit suicide. Similarly, a company knows that some people will use the roads they build to engage in reckless conduct that will kill innocent people.
Applied to the context under discussion, a person who kills a fetus causes the evils inflicted on the fetus, such things as, damage to the fetus’s bodily integrity and deprivation of their earthly life. However, these actions do not cause the fetus to attain eternal life; this is brought about by the gracious mercy of God. Hence when a person kills a fetus they do not benefit it, they only cause it harm.
In my next post in this series I will argue that Himma’s response to this line of argument fails.
1Kenneth Einar Himma “No Harm, No Foul: Abortion and the Implication of Fetal Innocence” 19:2 Faith and Philosophy (2002) 179.
2Loraine Boettner The Reformed Doctrine of Predestination by Loraine Boettner The Presbyterian and Reformed Publishing Company (Philadelphia, PA; 1963) 143.
3Ibid.
4Himma “No Harm No Foul” 179.
5Ibid 180.
6Ibid.
7Ibid.
8Mark Murphy “Pro-Choice and Presumption: A Reply to Kenneth Einar Himma” 20:2 Faith and Philosophy (2003) 241.
9Ibid.
10Alan Donagan “Moral Absolutism and the Double-Effect Exception: Reflections on Who Is Entitled to Double-Effect?” 16 Journal of Medicine and Philosophy (1991) 498.
11This is not to say that an agent acting unknowingly, such as the mail-man, is culpable for this action only that his actions are attributable to me. If I therefore do this willingly, I am culpable for his actions on my behalf while he is not.
12Theses situations are ones where one incites, induces or persuades a person to engage in wrongdoing or where in “pursuing his legitimate ends, a man finds that several effective courses of action are open to him, each legitimate in itself , but one of which will be foreseeable be met with a wrongful action by somebody else.” Alan Donagan The Theory of Morality (University of Chicago Press, Chicago; 1979) 48-50.
13 Augustine On Lying 9.
Tags: Abortion · Alan Donagan · Augustine · Eschatology · Feticide · Kenneth Einar Himma · Mark Murphy7 Comments
“However, these actions do not cause the fetus to attain eternal life; this is brought about by the gracious mercy of God.”
– Isn’t the “gracious mercy of God” a given and a constant in this situation?, therefore killing the fetus is sending it to heaven.
e.g., there is a competition at hospital, where the next person who comes in with a broken leg gets a billion dollars. If I break my friends leg, with the knowledge that he will get a billion dollars, I am doing something good for him, because the billion dollars is a given (same as getting into heaven).
[…] my previous post, Does Abortion Benefit the Fetus? A Critique of Himma Part 1, I discussed Kenneth Einar Himma’s argument that even if a fetus is a human being, laws […]
Some observations.
(1) Pascalian / Rawlsian
Himma’s scenario blends a version of Pascal’s wager (a person making rationally-guided choices with implications for the afterlife based solely on self-interest on accessing Heaven and avoiding Hell) with a neutral, disembodied perspective recommended in Rawls’s Theory of Justice (“Assume that you have no idea whatsoever of what your post-natal circumstances will be”) and then leaps to the assumption that making a life-or-death decision for a fetus is morally equivalent to making that decision for oneself. It equates abortion and suicide.
(2) Is Heaven guaranteed, or isn’t it?
I had the same reaction as the commenter Jerry. Himma’s thought experiment assumes that the person — whether it is a fetus, child, or adult facing death is irrelevant for the following objection — knows the choice is between instant death and guaranteed Heaven on one hand or a chance at life and a concomitant chance at Hell on the other hand. Therefore, Murphy’s objection doesn’t quite fit the scenario. Murphy says that “the causal chain from act to effect is broken by the intervention of a free agent”–in this case, killing does not lead to annihilation because God intervenes to send the victim to Heaven. Well, if the fact that God is ready to give another angel its wings is known to the murderer as well as the martyr, then we might say that the murderer actually kindly intends to send the victim to Heaven and not to annihilation.
(3) Euthanasia
Countless people actually have killed their family members in extreme circumstances such as illness or persecution, often with the conviction that the dead person would go to “a better place.” By making the basic assumption relevant to euthanasia (that the person is better off dead), this argument equates abortion and euthanasia.
(4) Does God have free will?
Does God have free will to choose to send a fetus to Hell? If He does, it is impossible for us to calculate the fetus’s rational self-interest as Himma’s scenario requires, since we can’t know for certain whether the dead fetus will really go to Heaven. If, on the other hand, God does not have free will in this situation, then we have contradicted Donagan’s claim that God’s manumission of the fetus to Heaven is “a free reaction to an action”. God is just a cog in the cosmic wheel and the ultimate responsibility for the fetus’s eternal welfare lies with the person who killed it.
(5) Consent and Moral Dignity
The consent of the victim usually carries moral weight. In Himma’s example, the fetus is magically granted a mature consciousness in order to consent to die based on its own rational self-interest. This is supposed to illustrate why other people should make the decision for the fetus. But there is a moral distinction here. Simply identifying the rational choice does not mean it is irrelevant who makes the choice. For example, it is in my rational self-interest to save part of my income for retirement, but should I choose not to do so, no one else has the right to steal my paycheck and invest it for me. There is a moral dignity in being allowed to make bad decisions; moral dignity is a value that is therefore distinct from rational self-interest. Granted, the fetus is not yet conscious or competent to make any decisions. But is there not more moral dignity accorded to the fetus in allowing it to live so that it will eventually be able to make its own moral choices, including poor or irrational ones, rather than assuming the right to make those decisions for it? This is not to say that a person’s moral dignity is the sole object of all moral decisions, only that it is one possible factor, and so we should not assume that rational self-interest is the object of all moral decisions, either.
(6) Slippery Slope
Just as moral permission for abortion of early-stage embryos may create a slippery slope for the age at which abortion or infanticide is no longer acceptable, the assumption that all embryos go to Heaven may create a slippery slope for the age at which a person is finally responsible for his or her eternal welfare. (You made a related observation in Part 2 of your blog post.) If we do not know when people become responsible for themselves, neither do we know when we cease to be responsible for them.
(7) Foreseeable result
In Augustine’s hypothetical situation, a man threatens to kill himself if a woman does not submit to sex with him. Is she responsible for his foreseeable death if she declines? Most would say no; the suicidal man bears full responsibility. But consider a real-world variant of this situation: There is a violent uprising and a leader must decide whether to take police or military intervention to restore peace. If military action is taken, some collateral damage is expected, but if nothing is done, possibly even more innocents will suffer at the hands of the mob. It is not enough for the leader to say, “Whatever violence the mob commits is its own fault; I bear no responsibility for it.” The leader has to make the difficult choice whether or not to send the army to forcibly shut down the riot, knowing that casualties are foreseeable either way. The leader has been placed in that situation through no personal fault yet nevertheless shares the moral burden. The moral burden is not attached solely to the “free choice” of the mob. To return to the main topic: If the fate of another person’s soul is foreseeable, then the person who foresees it bears some moral responsibility for it. I do not personally believe that we can know or foresee anything about the afterlife, but that is different than saying that we foresee someone’s fate yet bear no moral responsibility for it.
Jerry wrote “Isn’t the “gracious mercy of God” a given and a constant in this situation?, therefore killing the fetus is sending it to heaven.”
I am inclined to think this is false, you do not “send the fetus to heaven” God does this, You simply kill the fetus.
“ there is a competition at hospital, where the next person who comes in with a broken leg gets a billion dollars. If I break my friends leg, with the knowledge that he will get a billion dollars, I am doing something good for him, because the billion dollars is a given (same as getting into heaven).”
Again I am inclined to think not for the reasons outlined in the post above. The person who donates the a million dollars does something good for your friend. It’s really up to him not you whether your friend is benefited. What you do is break your friend’s leg, you do this knowing someone else will benefit him, but you yourself do not confer this benefit on him someone else does.
.-= My last blog-post ..Top 10 NZ Christian Blogs – October 09 =-.
“yourself do not confer this benefit on him someone else does.”
I agree witht his Matt. The reason why others might not, of course, is that they are thinking purely in consequentialist terms, and given that line of thought, as has been said by Jonathan Glover, “It makes no difference whether or not I do it.” As long as we know what will happen in the end, the actual awfulness of our actions makes no moral difference, which seems enormously counter-intuitive to me (and hopefully a few other people!).
.-= My last blog-post ..Nuts and Bolts 005: Ethical Naturalism =-.
Matt & Glenn,
The question of foreseeable consequences and God’s role as a free agent is discussed in Part 2 of this blog post.
I doubt that many people are pure consequentialists; it’s contrary to common sense to think that our personal decisions have no moral value, as long as everything turns out all right in the end. On the other end of the spectrum, I don’t think many people are pure intentionalists, either; it’s also contrary to common sense to think that the most moral lifestyle is that of a self-righteous purist who doesn’t care if he hurts everyone around him.
What we think of as morality is a hybrid theory that usually blends good intentions with good results. Therefore, it’s relevant whether you think you know the fate of someone’s soul (the “result” of their death).
Some Christians believe it is their moral duty to convert others to Christianity to help them get “saved,” even though technically it’s God who does the saving. Isn’t it at least plausible, then, that someone could believe it is their moral duty to kill someone to help them go to Heaven, even though it’s God who does the saving?
The scenario of breaking a friend’s leg to confer a benefit upon him is not so fanciful as it may sound. People have maimed their friends (with their consent) to help them avoid being conscripted as soldiers. In this case, I don’t think it’s fair to foist all responsibility onto the draft board, claiming that the draft board has ultimate say on who stays and who goes. Realistically, if you broke your friend’s leg, you knew full well he wouldn’t be fighting on the front lines, and if that was your intention, you have accomplished it. The connection is obvious enough that the government might even hold you accountable for helping someone evade the draft, despite the fact that the government was ostensibly the one who made the decision not to take the maimed man. The draft board is made up of people who have “free will,” but since you influenced their decision to such a degree that you basically forced them to choose a certain way, you have moral responsibility for what they decided.
Christian Carnival: Happy New Year!…
Dr Matthew Flannagan presents Does Abortion Benefit the Fetus? A Critique of Himma Part 1 posted at MandM, … sets out an objection articulated by Mark Murphy, which appeals to the common law doctrine of novus actus interveniens….